substantial income disparities between social groups that might be sociallydisruptive. Similarly, the spatial concentration of copying can reinforce spatialdifferences in incomes.Pooling has more potential to be regressive, because it is reciprocal. Networkstend to include people with similar quantities of knowledge, because peoplewith a lot of knowledge will find it advantageous to pool with others who alsohave a lot of knowledge. Treating the quantity of knowledge as a constraint onwhich networks an agent can join, the incentive to join an information networkis greater the greater the amount of information in the network. People withlittle knowledge to share are thus confined to networking with others with littleknowledge, and so have less incentive to join a network than people withlarge quantities of knowledge. Pooling is therefore regressive in two ways:more knowledgeable people will have larger networks, and they will gain moreinformation from each contact in the network. In effect, pooling introduces anexponent term onto private knowledge. A tendency to exclude the poor is thusbuilt into private incentives to pool knowledge.The second externality is the reduction in opportunism, which is achievedthrough repeat transactions and reputation. Repeat transactions have the effectof socially excluding new entrants and so tend to disadvantage the poor.Reputation magnifies the gain from repeat transactions. Repeat transactionsproduce a promise–trust bilateral relationship; reputation enables those whoare in a promise–trust relationship to access many other transactions. Biggsand Srivastava (1996) show how this phenomenon hurts African-owned firmsrelative to Asian-owned firms in Kenya.The third effect is collective action, which is achieved through norms andrules. Some of these norms and rules apply across the society. Putnam’s choirs,for example, build trust not just among choir members but among the populationas a whole. Such social capital is likely to be proportionately more beneficialto the poor, who are less able to invest in substitutes. For example, an agentis protected against crime both by private expenditures on security and by thenorms and rules of society. Because the poor are less able to afford privatesecurity expenditures, they are more dependent on norms and rules. Generally,the victims of crime are disproportionately drawn from the poor (which probablyreflects differences in security expenditures), so that the stronger are norms andrules, the more the poor gain relative to the better-off.Other norms and rules apply only to the group. Thus the rules of a clubmay make it an effective agency for increasing the incomes of its members. Ingeneral, the poor have more to gain from norms and rules than higher-incomegroups and so have more incentive to join clubs and authorities. In credit transactions,for example, social sanction and collateral assets are alternative means
of reassuring lenders. Wealthy people do not need social sanction, whereas the
poor do. Similarly, the economies of scale that collective action facilitates are
đang được dịch, vui lòng đợi..